In the Beginning…

This is an attempt to give an account of my personal philosophy from the ground up. I’m doing this primarily for myself. I want a map of my brain. Also, in the event that anyone reads anything on this blog, I’d like them to have a map of my brain as well. I would hate for anyone to read any of this and go, “Maybe if I knew what this asshole thought about the nature of existence, I could decipher this gobbledy-gook he calls an essay about the effects of the Punic Wars on 9th wave feminism?”
Unfortunately, this is going to be a less than exhaustive effort, cos I got shit to do.  However, shit to do notwithstanding, this will hopefully keep me philosophically consistent, but failing that, it will give you enough to see where I went wrong.  Along with my thoughts and such, I will attempt to provide a partial account of the literature/film/music/experiences that I think led me to take up those thoughts.
Enjoy this handy bulleted list!
  1. Epistemology & Metaphysics

On Vote Markets

Christopher Freiman on Vote Markets at BHL.

(1) As noted, vote markets enable mutually beneficial exchange. Even if that’s not all that counts, it surely counts for something. That vote sales leave both buyers and sellers better off by their own lights is a reason to permit vote sales. Of course, vote sales can also impose costs on third parties. If Sally sells her vote to Brent, who proceeds to use it in support of an unjust, harmful, or otherwise bad candidate or policy, then citizens who are not part of the vote sale can be made worse off. But this point brings me to a second reason to allow vote markets.

(2) Citizens enjoy significant discretion in their use of their vote, including the ability to use their vote in ways that can generate negative externalities. After all, the state doesn’t ban Sally from voting directly for unjust, harmful, or otherwise bad candidates and policies. Since the state generally allows you to use your vote as you see fit, shouldn’t it allow you to sell your vote if you see fit to do so?

(3) Some economists have argued that vote markets enable electoral outcomes to reflect the intensity of citizens’ political preferences. Suppose 51% of the electorate just barelysupports Candidate A over Candidate B. The remaining 49% strongly prefer Candidate B to Candidate A. A vote market would enable supporters of B to buy votes, thus leading to the election of B—which is plausibly the preferable outcome in this election.

(4) Vote buying and selling is similar to other legally permissible democratic practices like earmarking, whereby candidates (promise to) allocate funds to specific projects or recipients to win a given portion of the electorate’s support. If a candidate can “buy” the support of voters by offering them $1,000 worth of subsidies, why can’t that candidate buy the support of voters by offering them $1,000 directly? (Even opponents of vote sales like Sandel recognize this similarity.) At this point, you’re probably thinking that candidates shouldn’t be allowed to buy the support of voters with pork. Fair enough. But if pork barreling and other forms of political favoritism are eliminated, then potential vote buyers would have no incentive to bring about the negative outcomes associated with vote markets—there would be no profit in buying up votes.

For many people, vote markets just don’t pass the smell test. “What an obvious ploy to allow the rich to exert even more influence on elections than they already do,” they might say or maybe, “But it’s the responsibility of citizens to vote for themselves.” As a thoroughly unprincipled person, I’m going to pass on taking the latter objection, but in response to the former, I have to say that these objections represent a pretty negative view of the decision making capabilities of poor people.

Given that people wouldn’t have to sell their vote to the first or highest bidder that came along, I think it’s erroneous to think that the vote markets would automatically favor the wealthy elite. It would likely be much less expensive for a person or organization to buy someone’s vote in favor of something that already aligned with their preferences than in favor of something that went against those preferences. The upside to this is that it would probably be impossibly expensive to buy enough votes to enact something wildly unpopular like segregation laws. While I’m a little less confident about it, I think a similar outcome would occur with things like crop subsidies. Though groups favoring crop subsidies would face lower organizing costs to coordinate buying votes for their preferred subsidies, any group opposed to crop subsidies that could successfully organize to buy opposing votes would likely do so at a lower cost, assuming of course that opposition to crop subsidies was the base preference of most people.

Now, especially wealthy vote buyers may still be able to overcome their opponents through sheer force of dollars in some instances, but even if that occurs we would only be back to the usual situation of the rich influencing votes in their favor only without campaign-industrial complex middle man.

On Campaign Contributions

As far as I can tell, people are really blowing the whole supreme court decision against the Watergate-era campaign contribution limits out of proportion. First of all, most of the literature on the effectiveness of campaign contributions suggests that they do very little to sway elections anyway and that contribution limits aren’t obviously associated with less corruption. Moreover, voters are even less likely to respond to campaign advertising of any kind in environments with no campaign contribution limits because they suspect that the advertising in those environments must be “dirty” and therefore untrustworthy. So, the removal of campaign contribution limits seems to have the counter-intuitive effect of making those contributions less effective.

Of course, I’m not saying that I’m pro-campaign contributions.  Campaign contributions are not generally good for anyone except the politician and potential buyers, but this decision, if it has an effect on things at all, represents only a very marginal increase in overall badness.  It’s akin to stubbing your toe when you’re dying of cancer.

Now some might say “Well, I don’t care about evidence.  Money in politics is bad, so there’s just gotta be some reasonable limit to campaign contributions.” A reasonable limit would be one which had the effect of preventing the offending behavior in question. In this case, that behavior is something like undue influence on either politicians or the citizenry through campaign advertising. Based on the available research, though, campaign contributions don’t seem to have the level of influence claimed by proponents of campaign contribution limits nor do campaign contribution limits seem to bring about less corrupt government. Perhaps new, more nuanced research will prove otherwise, but until such research arrives, there doesn’t seem to be a lot of backing for the necessity or efficacy of campaign contribution limits.

Far too many people assume that passing a law against something means that that something will stop. Here, the assumption is that if you put a limit on the amount of money a person can give to politicians, that person will stop giving money after they’ve reached that amount. This represents an understanding of the interplay between politicians and their financial supporters that lacks nuance. Really, what campaign contribution limits do is impose a barrier that limits further contributions to those funders who can successfully navigate the complex array of campaign finance laws in order to give money to their preferred candidate anyway. This could be through PACs, straight up back room envelope full of money deals, or who knows what else – I’m not a professional lobbyist. The juice, though, is that money is still going to politicians, but it’s only money from especially wealthy and crafty people, i.e. the supposed primary targets of campaign contribution limits.  As with a lot of regulation, campaign contribution limits mostly serve as a placebo.  They ease the public’s cognitive dissonance about continuing to work within a system which very clearly stopped serving them a long time ago, assuming it ever did, while maintaining the status quo as much as possible. After all, politicians and corporations worked really hard to gain access to all that wealth and power; it would be kinda silly for them to install actually effective limits on their ability to gain more wealth and power.